Lecture on Aquinas' Second and Third Way
2. What is Hick's way of reading this causal series?
3. How does Hick evaluate the argument?
4. Would Aquinas agree with Hick as Hick has interpreted the premises? Explain whether or not you yourself would agree so far.
5. Aquinas distinguishes between an accidentally ordered series of causes and an essentially ordered series of causes. Explain that distinction by analyzing examples of the two series.
6. Which series does Aquinas use as the basis of his proof?
7. If God is the cause of all actions in an essentially ordered series, how can human action avoid being forced and necessitated by God's causality?
8. What are the premises and conclusion of Aquinas' argmnent?
9. What is the logical structure of the argument? ls the structure valid or invalid? Explain
10. Explain whether or not the first premise is true?
11. Explain whether or not the second premise is true?
12. What objection does Hick raise against the argument? How does Aquinas agree or disagree with such an objection? (See earlier
part of lecture for Hick's analysis and the response of Aquinas.)
13. What serious objection to the second premise is noted by James Ross? What is one way of responding? What is another way of responding offered by Ross?
14. Also, discuss the response of the lecture to the problem raised by Ross that "too many philosophers, writing introductory texts, treat the argmnents for the existence of God as if they have little to offer the student"? Include an analysis of your own personal response
to the argument's claimed validity and the truth of the prermses.
Questions on the Third Way
15. What is the beginning point of the second way, and what is the beginning point of the third way? Then state the 3rd way of proving the existence of God in clear logical form.
16. What is the logical structure of the argmnent? Is it valid or invalid? Why?
17. Is the first premise true? Explain. (Evidence for the first premise is offered with paragraphs begiming: "The question now is…" and "In summary…"
18 Is the second premise true? That is, what argument does the teacher offer for the second premise?
19. How would Aquinas respond to the objection that he has shown that there exists a First Cause and a Necessary Being but not that God is the First Cause and Necessary Being? Give some indication of the analysis offered to respond to tbat objection.
20. Some basic principles of critical thinking are to develop:
first, valid arguments in deductive masoning (as Aquinas has attempted in his second and third ways) or strongly probable arguments in inductive reasoning; secondly, good evidence and/or logical analysis for the truth of the premises in an argument (as Aquinas has attempted im his second and third ways); thirdly, consistency and coherence amongst one's fundamental conclusions (as Aquinas has attempted in his second and third ways in striving for consistency and coherence in his concept of the First Cause and the Necessary Ground of Existence as God, the spiritual being infiinitely perfect in knowledge arnd freedom); and fourthly, agreement with well accepted truths in the sciences and the humanities (as Aquinas has attempted in his second and third ways in rejecting as invalid an argument from a temporal series of cause and effects going back in time to a supposed Cause of the Big Bang).
Please explain fully how your thinking about God (whether you are a theistic, a pantheist, an agnostic, or an atheist) also exemplies each of the four key principles of critical thinking noted above. Number your answers 1 to 4, continuing your answers fully on the next page:
Thomas Aquinas' Second Way of Proving the Existence of God
Aquinas, like Descartes, accepts the principle of efficient causality as self-evident The principle is expressed in
the text by Aquinas as "There is no case known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be the
efficient cause of itself, for so it would be prior to itself, which is impossible." In othor words, a thing which begins
to be must have a cause of its beginning to be. It is impossible for a non-existent thing to make itself existent. It is
impossible for non-being to cause being. Being cannot come from nothingness. That is, it is self-evident that being
cannot come to be from nonbeing.
Aquinae states his second way of proving the existence of God in the text, p. 135. This second way concludes to
God as the First Efficient Cause of a series of causes. There are two ways of interpreting this argument.
The first way of interpreting the argument is exemplified by John Hick in his Philosophy of Religion, p. 20. Hick
writes:
Every thing that happens has a cause, and this cause in turn has a cause, and so on in a series which must
either be infinite or have its starting point in the first cause. Aquinas excludes the possibility of an infinite
series or regress of causes, and so he concludes that there must be a first cause, which we call God.
Hick is presenting the argument as though it went like thisBaby Joe Jones had a cause, namely, his parents.
Baby Joe Jones had a cause of his coming to be, namely, his parents.
His parents had their cause, namely, their grandparents.
The grandparents had their causes, namely, the great grandparents.
And so the argument would go, until we would reach the first cause of the whole series.
Now Hick argues that Aquinas does not exclude with good argument that this regress into the parents,
grandparents, and great grandparents cannot be an infinite regress. Hick claims that Aquinas does not show that
the world of matter and energy could not be eternal. If matter and energy are themselves eternally taking new
forms, then there would be no need to say that the regress into past causes must stop with a first cause. Hick says
that it is possible that God is the first cause of the world but that Aquinas' argument does not prove that point.
As Hick has interpreted the argument of Aquinas, his analysis is correct: Aquinas does not prove that there must
be a first cause for the series of causes of baby, parents, grandparents, great grandparents.
However, Hick has mis-interpreted the argument. In other writings Aquinas explicitly considers the kind of series
of causes Hick assumes and agrees with Hick's analysis that we cannot prove that such a series must have a First
Efficient Cause. These are the references which Hick has ignored: Summa Theologica, I, 46, 2, ad 7m; Summa
Contra Gentiles, I, ch . 12, second paragraph from end. In these texts, Aquinas distinguishes between an
accidentally ordered series of causes and an essentially ordered series of causes.
An accidentally ordered series of causes is one in which the causation does not reach down to the ultimate effect
with it being essential that the original or earlier causes still continue to operate. For example, if I light a match
and then light a candle with the match and then light a second candle with the first lit candle and then light a third
candle with the second candle, the fire of the match does not have to continue to exist; nor does it have to continue
to cause the first candle to be lit in order for the first candle to continue to burn. The match can go out, and the first
candle can go out even though the second and third candle stay lit. In an accidentally ordered series of causes such
as the candles, the earlier candles can burn out even though more candles continue to be lit in the series. So the
earlier or even the first in the series cannot be proven to be still in existence. In such a series, there is no need to
conclude to a first efficient cause.
The insight into the baby Joe Jones--parent-grandparent series of causes is similar. The grandparents do not have
to be still alive for the parents to make the baby Joe Jones. It is possible that there can be a First Efficient Cause
still existing, but we cannot prove that there ids a first nor that it continues to exist. By faith, Aquinas believed that
God created the world at the beginning of time because of the opening line of the book of Genesis: "In the
beginning (of time) God created heaven and earth. Yet, Aquinas does not affirm that he can prove by natural
reason that God created the world at the beginning of time. He cannot prove that God is the First Efficient Cause
of an accidentally ordered series of causes.
However, Aquinas does affirm that he can prove the existence of God as the First efficient Cause of an essentially
ordered series of causes. In an essentially ordered series of causes, the causality of the first in the series extended
all the way through the intermediary causes to the last effect. Such a series differs from an accidentally ordered
series of causes in which the causality of the first, for example, the match, is not required to be existing and still
operating in order for the third candle to be lit. An example of an essentially ordered series of causes would be
this:
My mind and will direct my arm to move a piece of chalk.
My arm moves a piece of chalk against the blackboard.
The chalk leaves the effect of an English sentence on the blackboard.
In this series, my mind and will, my arm, and the chalk, the first in the series, namely my mind and will, is required
to be in existence and to be operating in order for the other causes in the series to be operating. If I were to have a
stroke, the chalk would cease writing an English sentence on the board and would fall to the ground or scratch a
scribble across the board. The sentence would not be completed if the first cause ceased to operate. In an
essentially ordered series, every cause in the series is essential here and now for the series to continue to operate.
If the mind-will-arm-chalk series of causes is an essentially ordered series of causes, then we have to conclude,
affirms Aquinas, that this series has a First Efficient Cause, which people call God. Thus this series would really be
God, my mind and will, my arm, and the chalk That God is the ultimate cause of this series does not mean for
Aquinas that the human being is not free. For God causes my mind and will in such a way that I am a rational and
free being capable of deliberation in my thought and free choice in my will. God causes things to happen in accord
with the nature of each thing. Irrational animals and natural forces have no intelligence and freedom. They bring
about their effects through causal necessity. But human nature is capable of rational and free action, and God
causes human beings to act in accord with people's own rational deliberation and free choice.
To conclude to a First Efficient Cause of such a series, it is required that Aquinas eliminate an infinite regress. The
infinite or endless regression into causes in the past was all right in an accidentally ordered series of causes but
not in an essentially ordered series of causes for two reasons:
First, all the causes of the series are in act, in simultaneous act, here and now actually producing the effect,
either bringing it into being or keeping it in being . Secondly, such a cause is essentially ordered to the cause
above it, because it is here and now receiving from the cause above it the power by which it operates as
cause. Now if we were to proceed infinitely in causes that receive their causality from another, we would
always be dealing with causes that are intermediate causes that are moved to their causality. Hence to say
there is no first cause is to affirm and deny being at the same time. For on the on hand we affirm that all
these intermediate causes have received an influence from another, and on the other hand we say they have
not received it, since we deny there is a first from which they have received it. Since, de facto (as a matter of
fact), the ultimate effect does exist, then de jure (as a matter of right), there must exist a first cause which
does not receive influence from another but is the cause of the influence received in those intermediary
causes. Hence it is necessary to posit a first uncaused cause. (Klubertanz & Holloway, Being and God, p.
246)
To say that the First Cause is First means that its act of causing is not received from another being; its causality is
uncaused. Since the first cause of an essentially ordered series must be uncaused, my mind and my will cannot be
the first cause it its series. For my mind and will can be affected by outside causes. But the First Efficient Cause as
first must be uncaused, must have no potentiality for being caused.
In summary: the logical structure of Aquinas' second way of proving the existence of God is valid
(1) If there exists an essentially ordered series of efficient causes and if an infinite regression in such causes
is impossible (intellectually absurd), then such a series has a First Efficient Cause whose act of causality is
uncaused.
(2) There does exist an essentially ordered series of causes, and an infinite regression in such causes is
impossible.
(3) Therefore, such a series has a First Efficient Cause whose act of causality is uncaused.
If premises 1 and 2 are true, then the conclusion must be true since it has the logical form:
If A is true, then B is true.
A is true.
Therefore B follows with necessity.
We have considered evidence for the key second premise, offering examples of an accidentally ordered series of
causes and of an essentially ordered series of causes. Also, we offered reasons why an infinite regression in an
accidentally ordered series is possible but not in an essentially ordered series.
A serious objection to Aquinas' view that infinite regression in an essentially ordered series is impossible is noted
by James Ross:
St Thomas did not know that there can be an infinite series which has both a first and a last member. I have
in mind the set of all real numbers between 1 and 2, or the number of points between and including an
arbitrarily selected A and B on a line segment. Both series have first and last numbers, and yet an infinity of
elements. (Philosophy of Religion, p. 35)
Ono way of responding to this objection would be to say that the infinite number of points between two points on a
line is not an essentially ordered series. The points on the line are accidentally related to other points on the line.
The first point can exist without any necessary or essential connection with third or fourth point on the line. Also,
we can compare the points on a line with the moments in time in the accidentally ordered series of baby Joe Jones,
parents, grandparents, and great grandparents. In the time-line of parents and other ancestors, Aquinas says that
an infinite regression is of moments at which the causes are at work is possible. However, in an essentially ordered
series of efficient causes, such an infinite regression would be impossible.
Another way of responding to the objection is offered by Ross. Ross says that it doesn't matter whether the series
of causes is finite or infinite in an essentially ordered series of causes. For an infinite series can have a first
member and a last member. For example, the series of real numbers between 1 and 2 has a beginning, the number
1, and an end, the number 2. So also, God would be the first member of the series of essentially ordered causes in
writing the sentence on the board, and the sentence on the board would be the last member. There has to be a first
cause whose causality is uncaused in order to explain the causes which have received their causality. Ross argues
that the causal activity in the later elements of the series of essentially order causes is dependent on the
simultaneous activity of everything that precedes it. If the activity of the combined members is nit accounted for by
the fact that they include one member which is uncaused by another causes, then the activity of the combined
preceding members is not accounted for at all or is accounted for by some cause not in the series. In the latter
case, there is an uncaused first cause which is not a member of the series. In the former cases, there is no
explanation for the existence and activity of the causes in the series, and in fact the causes in the series are
impossible [unintelligible] pp. 35-36
Ross is agreeing with the insight of the argument of Aquinas. Whether the series of essentially ordered causes be
a finite series or an infinite series, there must be a first uncaused cause of the simultaneous causality in that
series. If there be no such uncaused cause, then all the causes in that series are receiving their causality; but no
first cause is giving such causality. Such a situation is intellectually contradictory. Hence, there must be a first
efficient cause whose causality is uncaused.
After analyzing the classical arguments for the existence of God, of which Aquinas' second way is one example,
Ross writes:
Conclusion: Too many philosophers, writing introductory texts, treat the arguments for the existence of God as if
they have little to offer the student. They adopt a patronizing, rational agnosticism, apparently equally critical of all
the arguments for the existence of God and all those against, an attitude which loads the student to expect little
from the whole process of argumentation. (p.56)
Ross believes that there is a great deal to be said in defense of the arguments, just as he has defended Aquinas'
second way. He notes that more objections can be raised against the proofs for the new student in philosophy by
one who is more skilled in philosophy. The new student, however, should not be dismayed. For any given argument
in philosophy, whether in morality, or human freedom, or in questions about God, it is true that there are many
questions to be asked of the premises in those arguments. For example, in dealing with morality, we could
challenge the assumption of Aristotle and Mill that all our actions are directed toward happiness. We could
challenge the assumption that ethical principles should be based on the desire for happiness. In dealing with
determinism and freedom, we could challenge the assumption of behaviorism that human behavior can be
understood as though it were animal behavior. We could challenge the assumption of Rogers that self-awareness is
a trustworthy source of insight into our personal freedom. And finally in dealing with Thomas Aquinas' Second
Way, we could challenge his assumption that there is a difference between an accidentally ordered series of causes
and an essentially ordered series of causes. We could challenge his assumption of the fact that there does exist an
essentially ordered series of causes. We did challenge his assumption about an infinite regression being impossible
and noted how Aquinas could still respond to that challenge. There are so many more challenges and objections
and questions which we could have raised.
The point for the new student is not to be dismayed. Underlying the act of our doing philosophy is a trust in our own
humanity. There is a trust in our human experience and a trust in our human capabilities. We examine various
approaches we select the best approach so far as we know up to this point, but the important point is to be open to
further exploration and dialogue with others. We need not be dismayed that people argue differently about moral
principles, about determinism and freedom, and about God. For we realize that we do not start with objective
evidence and with absolute principles of knowledge. The various methods philosophers use affect the evidences
they find and guide them in interpreting those evidences. We need to work towards clarification of our own values
and beliefs, towards understanding of the values and beliefs of others, and towards the values implicit in the
clarification and dialogue that philosophy involves.
Thomas Aquinas' Third Way of Proving the Existence of God
The third way of proving the existence of God has been called the argument from the contingency of being and also
the cosmological argument. This argument differs from the second way in that the second way argues from the fact
of the existence of an essentially ordered series of causes to God as the First Cause of that series whereas the
third way argues from the fact of the existence of contingent beings to God the Necessary Being who is the cause
of contingent beings to God the Necessary Being who is the cause of their being. Both arguments begin with a
sensible fact as interpreted by the mind and conclude to God as the cause of that fact. In the second way, we begin
with the fact of an essentially ordered series of causes and conclude to God as the First Cause of Causality: in the
third way, we begin with the fact of contingent beings and conclude to God, the Necessary Being, who is the cause
of contingent beings.
The third way can be stated in the following valid form:
Premise 1: If contingent beings exist and if contingent beings cannot be the sufficient reason or cause of
their continuing to be, then only a Necessary Being can be the sufficient explanation of their continuing to
be.
Premise 2: Contingent beings do exist, and they cannot be the sufficient reason or cause of their continuing
to be.
Conclusion: Therefore, only a Necessary Being can be the sufficient explanation of their continuing to be.
The argument has the valid form:
If P, then Q.
P is true.
Therefore, Q is true.
If the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true in this valid form. It has the same va;id form as thr
argument from the second way. If, whenever p happens, q happens, and if p did happen, then q has to have
happened.
The question is whether the premises are true. It is obvious that contingent beings do exist. Contingent beings are
beings which come to be and which cease to be. There are obvious examples such as cats, dogs, human beings, and
even species.
In this argument, Aquinas is not arguing that God is the cause of the beginning to be of such beings,, The Third
way is not the second way. In the second way, Aquinas argued that there could be an infinite regress in an
accidentally ordered series of causes of the beginning to be of causality. He also argued that there could not be
such a regress in an essentially ordered series of causes of the beginning to be of essentially ordered causality and
of the continuing to be of such causality. If at any time God ceased to exercise his act of causality in my mind and
will-arm-hand-chalk series of writing an English sentence on the board, then the causality of that series would
cease to be?
In attempting to establish the second part of premise 2, Aquinas employs a distinction between the essence of a
being and the existence of the being. The essence of the being is known in the definition of the being; the definition
identifies what the being is. For example, a human being is a rational animal (a being whose purpose or goal is to
be rational and free, wise and loving).
As Sartre pointed out, the essence of a being can be defined even though the being does not exist. For we can
know the purpose of a being and the means to that purpose before the being is made to exist. The existence of a
being is known in what Aquinas calls the judgment of existence. For example, we either affirm or deny that a
human being exists. In sumary, essence is known in a definition that takes the following form of our example: a
human being is a rational animal. And existence is known in a judgment of existence that takes the following form
for our example: a human being exists. Essence refers to what a being is, whereas existence refers to that a being
is.
Aquinas argues that contingent beings, beings which come to be and which pass away, are beings in which there is
a real distinction between their essence and their existence. This is the argument of Aquinas:
Premise 1: If it were of the essence of a contingent being to exist, then a contingent being would not be able
not to exist. ("If a thing accounts for its own continuing to exist by virtue of what sort of thing it is, then it
would not be possible it not-to-be, since in order for it not to be it would have to cease to be of the sort that it
is (it would have to cease to be what it essentially is). In other words, if Socrates were of such a sort
(essence), e.g., a human being, that he existed because of what he was, then in order not to exist he would
have to become non-human and this is impossible because Socrates, whether existing or not, it is essentially
a human." Ross, p. 63)
Premise 2: A contingent being is able not to exist. (For example, Socrates has ceased to exist.)
Conclusion: Therefore, it is not of the essence of a contingent being to exist. In other words, contingent
beings cannot be the sufficient reason or explanation of their continuing to be. Even while contingent beings
continue to exist, their existence is a continuing effect being received from a cause of existence. For the
essence of contingent beings is not a sufficient reason for the continuing existence of such beings.
The question now is: Could another contingent being be the continuing cause of another contingent beings
continuing to exist? The answer of Aquinas is that an infinite series of contingent beings cannot be the sufficient
reason or cause of the continuing to exist of Socrates. For those contingent beings would receiving their act of
causing being. That would be a contradiction that all the causes would be receiving their causality but no first cause
would be giving causality. An infinite regress of essentially ordered causes of the continuing to exist of contingent
beings is intellectually absurd. There must be a Necessary Being whose Essence it is To Exist. Only such a
necessarily existent being could be the sufficient reason for the continuing existence of contingent beings.
In summary:
If contingent being Y were the cause of the continuing to exist of contingent being Z, then Y would also need
to be explained. For any contingent being would not of its essence exist. Any contingent being's continuing to
exist is an effect and requires an explanation.
An infinite series of contingent beings than could not explain the continuing to exist of such beings.
Hence there must be a Necessary Being whose Essence is identical with Existence, whose Essence it is To
Exist; in other words, there must be a being whose essence requires that it necessarily exist.
An Objection
Sometimes the objection is made that Aquinas has shown that there exists a First Cause and Necessary
Being, but not that God is the First Cause and Necessary Being.
The Answer
Aquinas is only naming the First Cause and Necessary Being to be God at this stage of his argument. His
students knew that he would later show in his lectures by further argument that the First Cause and
Necessary Being are in fact the Almighty Good Being that humans worship.
One 19th Century writer, Cardinal Newman, outlines how one may show that the First Cause and Necessary Being
are God:
Since God is First Cause (and Necessary Being)….he differs from all his creatures in possessing existence a
se, (that is by himself). From this "a se-ity" (that is, from his uncaused possession of his own necessary
existence) on God's part, theology deduces by mere logic most of his other perfections. For instance, he
must be both necessary and absolute, cannot not be, and cannot in any way be determined by anything else.
This makes him absolutely unlimited from without, and unlimited also from within; for limitation is no-being;
and God is being itself (the being whose essence is to exist necessarily and as uncaused by any being). This
unlimitedness makes God infinitely perfect. Moreover, God is One and Only, for the infinitely perfect can
admit no peer. (Newman, The Idea of a University)
In summary, Newman's argument is valid:
If limitation is a way of restricting being, then the Necessary Being unlimited .
Limitation is a way of restricting being.
Therefore, the Necessary Being is unlimited.
If the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true. Newman argues that the premises are true. The first
premise is true conditionally. For as the being whose essence it is to exist necessarily and without causality from
any other being, the Necessary Being cannot be limited by any other being, cannot be affected by any other being.
And the second premise is true. For limitation is a way of restricting being. For example, blindness is a limitation in
that it is a restriction of vision; blindness involves loss of sight. In summary, God as the necessary being cannot
have limitation upon his being for he is the Being whose Essence is Necessary Existence.
Newman goes on to argue:
If the Necessary Being is unlimited, then it is infinitely Perfect.
The Necessary Being is unlimited.
Therefore, the Necessary Being is infinitely perfect.
This argument has the same valid form. If its premises are true, its conclusion must be true. The first premise is
true for Newman because if the necessary being is unlimited being, then it must be infinite (limited) perfection or
goodness. For evil is a loss of being or a restriction of being; for example, blindness is evil as a loss of sight. But
God as the Necessary Being cannot lose Being; God as the uncaused Cause cannot be caused by another being to
lost his causality and the second premise is true as the conclusion of the preceding valid argument.
Finally, Newman can argue validly:
If God is infinite being, then God is One and Only.
God is infinite being.
Therefore, God is One and Only.
If the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. The second premise is taken from the conclusions of the
preceding arguments. The first premise is true for Newman. For if there could be two infinite beings, two infinitely
perfect beings, then the infinite power of each one would be a limit on the other, which is impossible for the infinite
being cannot be limited. Hence God is One and Unique.
So, Newman, drawing upon the approach of Aquinas shows us the answer of Aquinas to the objection that Aquinas
only assumes that the first cause and necessary being is God.
In the next lecture on Hume, we will continue the philosophy of religion section by an analysis of Hume's theory of
knowledge and his rejection of proofs for God's existence. We shall see that he will challenge the heart of the
arguments of Descartes and Aquinas. For Hume will question their concept of efficient causality. Hume will argue
that we have no such rational insight into causality and that we cannot use the idea of causality as the basis of
proof for God.
LINKS
Western Philosophical Concepts of God Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Anselm
Aquinas, Thomas
Augustine
Is the proposition "God exists" self-evident? Aquinas's Evaluation of Anselm's Argument
Deduction and Induction
Whether God exists? The Five Ways of Aquinas for proving the Existence of God, Summa Theologica
Thomas Aquinas from Catholic Encyclopedia
Q&A excerpts from Radio Replies, on the Existence and Nature of God
Confessions of St Augustine
City of God by St. Augustine
The Resurrection of Thomism: Five Ways--his arguments for the existence of God.
PHILOSOPHY AND BELIEF IN GOD: THE RESURGENCE OF THEISM IN PHILOSOPHICAL CIRCLES
The Atheism Web: Research Bibliography
Natural Theology from Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Section 5: The Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God from Kant's Critique of
Pure Reason
William O'Meara's World of Philosophy & Religion
William O'Meara (c) Copyright, 1997